The
term "Stoicism" derives from the Greek word "stoa," referring to a colonnade,
such as those built outside or inside temples, around dwelling-houses,
gymnasia, and market-places. They were also set up separately as ornaments
of the streets and open places. The simplest form is that of a roofed colonnade,
with a wall on one side, which was often decorated with paintings. Thus
in the market-place at Athens the stoa poikile (Painted Colonnade) was
decorated with Polygnotus's representations of the destruction of Troy,
the fight of the Athenians with the Amazons, and the battles of Marathon
and Oenoe. Zeno of Citium taught in the stoa poikile in Athens, and his
adherents accordingly obtained the name of Stoics. Zeno was followed by
Cleanthes, and then by Chrysippus, as leaders of the school. The school
attracted many adherents, and flourished for centuries, not only in Greece,
but later in Rome, where the most thoughtful writers, such as Marcus Aurelius,
Seneca, and Epictetus, counted themselves among its followers.
We
know little for certain as to what share particular Stoics, Zeno, Cleanthes,
or Chrysippus, had in the formation of the doctrines of the school, But
after Chryssipus the main lines of the doctrine were complete. The stoic
doctrine is divided into three parts: logic, physics, and ethics. Stoicism
is essentially a system of ethics which, however, is guided by a logic
as theory of method, and rests upon physics as foundation. Briefly, their
notion of morality is stern, involving a life in accordance with nature
and controlled by virtue. It is an ascetic system, teaching perfect indifference
(apathea) to everything external, for nothing external could be either
good or evil. Hence to the Stoics both pain and pleasure, poverty and riches,
sickness and health, were supposed to be equally unimportant.
Stoic
Logic
Stoic
logic is, in all essential, the logic of Aristotle. To this, however, they
added a theory, peculiar to themselves, of the origin of knowledge and
the criterion of truth. All knowledge, they said, enters the mind through
the senses. The mind is a blank slate, upon which sense- impressions are
inscribed. It may have a certain activity of its own, but this activity
is confined exclusively to materials supplied by the physical organs of
sense. This theory stands, of course, in sheer opposition to the idealism
of Plato, for whom the mind alone was the a source of knowledge, the senses
being the source of knowledge, the senses being the sources of all illusion
and error. The Stoics denied the metaphysical reality of concepts. Concepts
are merely ideas in the mind, abstracted from particulars, and have no
reality outside consciousness.
Since
all knowledge is a knowledge of sense-objects, truth is simply the correspondence
of our impressions to things. How are we to know whether our ideas are
correct copies of things? How do we distinguish between reality and imagination,
dreams, or illusions? What is the criterion of truth? It cannot lie in
concepts, since they are of our own making. Nothing is true save sense
impressions, and therefore the criterion of truth must lie in sensation
itself. It cannot be in thought, but must be in feeling. Real objects,
said the Stoics, produce in us an intense feeling, or conviction, of their
reality. The strength and vividness of the image distinguish these real
perceptions from a dream or fancy. Hence the sole criterion of truth is
this striking conviction, whereby the real forces itself upon our consciousness,
and will not be denied. There is, thus, no universally grounded criterion
of truth. It is based, not on reason, but on feeling.
Stoic
Physics
The
fundamental proposition of the Stoic physics is that "nothing incorporeal
exists." This materialism coheres with the sense-impression orientation
of their doctrine of knowledge. Plato placed knowledge in thought, and
reality, therefore, in the ideal form. The Stoics, however, place knowledge
in physical sensation, and reality -- what is known by the senses -- is
matter. All things, they said, even the soul, even God himself, are material
and nothing more than material. This belief they based upon two main considerations.
Firstly, the unity of the world demands it. The world is one, and must
issue from one principle. We must have a monism. The idealism of Plato
resolved itself into a futile struggle involving a dualism between matter
and thought. Since the gulf cannot be bridged from the side of ideal realm
of the forms, we must take our stand on matter, and reduce mind to it.
Secondly, body and soul, God and the world, are pairs which act and react
upon one another. The body, for example, produces thoughts (sense impressions)
in the soul, the soul produces movements in the body. This would be impossible
if both were not of the same substance. The corporeal cannot act on the
incorporeal, nor the incorporeal on the corporeal. There is no point of
contact. Hence all must be equally corporeal.
All
things being material, what is the original kind of matter, or stuff, out
of which the world is made? The Stoics turned to Heraclitus for an answer.
Fire logos) is the primordial kind of being, and all things are composed
of fire. With this materialism the Stoics combined pantheism. The primal
fire is God. God is related to the world exactly as the soul to the body.
The human soul is likewise fire, and comes from the divine fire. It permeates
and penetrates the entire body, and, in order that its interpenetration
might be regarded as complete, the Stoics denied the impenetrability of
matter. Just as the soul-fire permeates the whole body, so God, the primal
fire, pervades the entire world.
But
in spite of this materialism, the Stoics declared that God is absolute
reason. This is not a return to idealism, and does not imply the incorporeality
of God. For reason, like all else, is material. It means simply that the
divine fire is a rational element. Since God is reason, it follows that
the world is governed by reason, and this means two things. It means, firstly,
that there is purpose in the world, and therefore, order, harmony, beauty,
and design. Secondly, since reason is law as opposed to the lawless, it
means that universe is subject to the absolute sway of law, is governed
by the rigorous necessity of cause and effect. Hence the individual is
not free. There can be no true freedom of the will in a world governed
by necessity. We may, without harm, say that we choose to do this or that,
and that our acts are voluntary. But such phrases merely mean that we assent
to what we do. What we do is none the less governed by causes, and therefore
by necessity.
The
world-process is circular. God changes the fiery substance of himself first
into air, then water, then earth. So the world arises. But it will be ended
by a conflagration in which all things will return into the primal fire.
Thereafter, at a pre-ordained time, God will again transmute himself into
a world. It follows from the law of necessity that the course taken by
this second, and every subsequent, world, will be identical in every way
with the course taken by the first world. The process goes on for ever,
and nothing new ever happens. The history of each successive world is the
same as that of all the others down to the minutest details.
The
human soul is part of the divine fire, and proceeds into humans from God.
Hence it is a rational soul, and this is a point of cardinal importance
in connection with the Stoic ethics. But the soul of each individual does
not come direct from God. The divine fire was breathed into the first man,
and thereafter passed from parent to child in the act of procreation. After
death, all souls, according to some, but only the souls of the good, according
to others, continue in individual existence until the general conflagration
in which they, and all else, return to God.
Stoic
Ethics
The
Stoic ethical teaching is based upon two principles already developed in
their physics; first, that the universe is governed by absolute law, which
admits of no exceptions; and second, that the essential nature of humans
is reason. Both are summed up in the famous Stoic maxim, "Live according
to nature." For this maxim has two aspects. It means, in the first place,
that men should conform themselves to nature in the wider sense, that is,
to the laws of the universe, and secondly, that they should conform their
actions to nature in the narrower sense, to their own essential nature,
reason. These two expressions mean, for the Stoics, the same thing. For
the universe is governed not only by law, but by the law of reason, and
we, in following our own rational nature, are ipso facto conforming ourselves
to the laws of the larger world. In a sense, of course, there is no possibility
of our disobeying the laws of nature, for we, like all else in the world,
act of necessity. And it might be asked, what is the use of exhorting a
person to obey the laws of the universe, when, as part of the great mechanism
of the world, we cannot by any possibility do anything else? It is not
to be supposed that a genuine solution of this difficulty is to be found
in Stoic philosophy. They urged, however, that, though we will in any case
do as the necessity of the world compels us, it is given to us alone, not
merely to obey the law, but to assent to our own obedience, to follow the
law consciously and deliberately, as only a rational being can.
Virtue,
then, is the life according to reason. Morality is simply rational action.
It is the universal reason which is to govern our lives, not the caprice
and self-will of the individual. The wise man consciously subordinates
his life to the life of the whole universe, and recognizes himself as a
cog in the great machine. Now the definition of morality as the life according
to reason is not a principle peculiar to the Stoics. Both Plato and Aristotle
taught the same. In fact, it is the basis of every ethic to found morality
upon reason, and not upon the particular foibles, feelings, or intuitions,
of the individual self. But what was peculiar to the Stoics was the narrow
and one- sided interpretation which they gave to this principle. Aristotle
had taught that the essential nature of humans is reason, and that morality
consists in following this, his essential nature. But he recognized that
the passions and appetites have their place in the human organism. He did
not demand their suppression, but merely their control by reason. But the
Stoics looked upon the passions as essentially irrational, and demanded
their complete extirpation. They envisaged life as a battle against the
passions, in which the latter had to be completely annihilated. Hence their
ethical views end in a rigorous and unbalanced asceticism.
Aristotle,
in his broad and moderate way, though he believed virtue alone to possess
intrinsic value, yet allowed to external goods and circumstances a place
in the scheme of life. The Stoics asserted that virtue alone is good, vice
alone evil, and that all else is absolutely indifferent. Poverty, sickness,
pain, and death, are not evils. Riches, health, pleasure, and life, are
not goods. A person may commit suicide, for in destroying his life he destroys
nothing of value. Above all, pleasure is not a good. One ought not to seek
pleasure. Virtue is the only happiness. And people must be virtuous, not
for the sake of pleasure, but for the sake of duty. And since virtue alone
is good, vice alone evil, there followed the further paradox that all virtues
are equally good, and all vices equally evil. There are no degrees.
Virtue
is founded upon reason, and so upon knowledge. Hence the importance of
science, physics, logic, which are valued not for themselves, but because
they are the foundations of morality. The prime virtues, and the root of
all other virtues, is therefore wisdom. The wise man is synonymous with
the good man. From the root-virtue, wisdom, spring the four cardinal virtues:
insight, bravery, self-control, and justice. But since all virtues have
one root, those who possess wisdom possess all virtue, and those who lack
it lack all. A person is either wholly virtuous, or wholly vicious. The
world is divided into wise and foolish people, the former perfectly good,
the latter absolutely evil. There is nothing between the two. There is
no such thing as a gradual transition from one to the other. Conversion
must be instantaneous. the wise person is perfect, has all happiness, freedom,
riches, beauty. They alone are the perfect kings, politicians, poets, prophets,
orators, critics, and physicians. The fool has all vice, all misery, all
ugliness, all poverty. And every person is one or the other. Asked where
such a wise person was to be found, the Stoics pointed doubtfully at Socrates
and Diogenes the Cynic. The number of the wise, they thought, is small,
and is continually growing smaller. The world, which they painted in the
blackest colors as a sea of vice and misery, grows steadily worse.
The
similarities between Cynicism and Stoic ethics are apparent. However, the
Stoics modified and softened the harsh outlines of Cynicism. To do this
meant inconsistency, though. It meant that they first laid down harsh principles,
and then proceeded to tone them down, to explain them away, to admit exceptions.
Such inconsistency the stoics accepted with their habitual cheerfulness.
This process of toning down their first harsh utterances took place mainly
in three ways. First, the modified their principle of the complete suppression
of the passions. Since this is impossible, and, if possible, could only
lead to immovable inactivity, they admitted that the wise person might
exhibit certain mild and rational emotions. Thus, the roots of the passions
might be found in the wise person, though they would never be allowed to
grow. In the second place, they modified their principle that all else,
save virtue and vice, is indifferent. Such a view is unreal, and out of
accord with life. Hence the stoics, with a masterly disregard of consistency,
stuck to the principle, and yet declared that among things indifferent
some are preferable to others. If the wise person has the choice between
health and sickness, health is preferable. Indifferent things were thus
divided into three classes: those to be preferred, those to be avoided,
and those which are absolutely indifferent.
In
the third place, the stoics toned down the principle that people are either
wholly good, or wholly evil. The famous heroes and politicians of history,
though fools, are yet polluted with the common vices of humankind less
than others. Moreover, what were the Stoics to say about themselves? Were
they wise men or fools? They hesitated to claim perfection, to put themselves
on a level with Socrates and Diogenes. Yet they could not bring themselves
to admit that there was no difference between themselves and the common
herd. They were "proficients," and, if not absolutely wise, approximated
to wisdom.
|